In
defending her view that abortion is at least some times permissible—in cases of
rape or in instances when the mother’s life is endangered by her pregnancy, for
instance—Judith J. Thompson advances a number of analogies to support her
position. In 1971’s A Defense of Abortion,
her analogies support her position by conceding the Argument from Personhood
and instead attack the premise of a fetus’ right-to-life.
Thompson’s
first analogy is to compare an unwanted pregnancy due to rape to one of us
being kidnapped and having us wake up to find a famous violinist attached to us
so that the violinist may use our kidneys to live. Thompson’s question is to
ask us if it is morally required of us to consent to our newfound condition. In
quoting the hypothetical doctor in her scenario, Thompson writes, “Violinists
are persons. Granted you have a right to decide what happens in and to your
body, but a person’s right to life outweighs your right to decide what happens
in and to your body.” Our intuition is that this is preposterous and indicates
there is something wrong with the right-to-life premise. This is because we
generally believe we are not morally obligated to aid someone against our will,
particularly when that aid requires an undue burden. As it applies to this
analogy, being forced to let the violinist to use our kidneys for one hour is
not an undue burden in the way that being forced to let the violinist use our
kidneys for nine months is. (There have been cases where a pregnant woman
alleges she didn’t know she was pregnant before birth or for months after being
impregnated. This wouldn’t seem to count as a burden if someone didn’t know
they were being burdened.) Nonetheless, having even one hour of kidney use be forced upon us would be a violation of
our negative [unalienable] rights, if we are inclined to believe in such
rights. Perhaps Thompson could have also argued for an undue burden insofar as
the rape victim being reminded every day of her ordeal. This would strengthen
the argument for allowing abortion in instances of rape.
In
instances when the mother’s life is endangered due to a pregnancy, Thompson
compares this to being trapped in a very tiny house with a rapidly growing
child. If we do not take action, we’ll be crushed to death by the child.
Earlier in her article, Thompson concedes that two lives may be equal in value,
but hints that this equality does not necessarily exclude one’s right to
self-defense. Thompson says that here, the proponents of a fetus’ right to life
are wrong to equate the mother’s life with “the status of a house, to which we
don’t allow the right of self-defense. But if the woman houses the child, it
should be remembered that she is the person who houses it.” However, Thompson
is careful to acknowledge that there are limits to self-defense but that this
circumstance is special, being that both persons are innocent and in a
situation neither has willed. For this reason, Thompson thinks it is
understandable not to let a third party intervene, but the person whose life is
threatened can. Unfortunately, Thompson doesn’t address the vital question of
who, if anyone, is allowed to defend the defenseless, especially when she has
conceded that a fetus is a person. If the situation is such that one person has
the ability to “defend” themselves and the other does not, her analogy suffers.
Finally,
Thompson defends abortion for those who have taken reasonable precautions
against pregnancy. She makes a comparison between (presumably reliable) birth
control methods and leaving a window open in a stuffy room through which a
burglar climbs. “It would be absurd to say, ‘Ah, now he can stay, she’s given
him the right to use her house—for she is partially responsible for his presence
there, having voluntarily done what enabled him to get in.’” Abortion would be
permissible in this case according to Thompson in order to preserve the quality
of a woman’s life which, we presume, includes having sex for pleasure. This
argument would give an unborn person a right to life so long as the potential
mother took no precautions along with the understanding that having sex might
result in a pregnancy. This would constitute a willful act on part of the woman
and such intentions are where a fetus’ right-to-life would arise from. Proving
a mother took no precautions along with the understanding that having sex might
result in a pregnancy may be difficult, however. Thompson’s attempt to preserve
a woman’s right to a certain quality of life hinges on the notion that it is
permissible for woman to have sex for pleasure, a notion not widely entertained
outside of Western cultures.
Thompson
defends abortion on the grounds that a fetus’ right-to-life is suspect on a
number of accounts, though some of those accounts are clearly stronger than
others. Foregoing the Argument from Personhood, Thompson built an interesting case
against a prohibition on abortion. If nothing else, Thompson taught us to go
beyond the Argument from Personhood to see if there are any grounds for allowing abortion. It appears there may very well
be.
No comments:
Post a Comment